BASIC RIGHTS SUBSISTENCE AFFLUENCE AND U.S.FOREIGN POLICY PDF

That is, without those rights to subsistence, physical security, and various liberties — for example, the liberty of effective participation — no other rights can be enjoyed or exercised by a people. Shue argues then that if one lacks subsistence — and therefore the capability to sustain human life — then he or she cannot enjoy any rights at all, for he or she is threatened by the inability to sustain his or her life. The author notes that economic and basic subsistence rights are predominantly perceived as positive rights in that they require more action on the part of other people than do negative rights. Shue provides substantive responses — thoughtfully demonstrated with explicit examples — to the three primary arguments that he perceives as challenges to the notion that subsistence rights ought to be considered basic human rights.

Author:Feshakar Zoloshakar
Country:Greece
Language:English (Spanish)
Genre:Technology
Published (Last):21 April 2005
Pages:178
PDF File Size:13.65 Mb
ePub File Size:16.12 Mb
ISBN:558-2-14679-466-5
Downloads:31258
Price:Free* [*Free Regsitration Required]
Uploader:Fenrilkree



Foreign Policy, Henry Shue argues that everyone has a right to subsistence and that this right is as important as the right to physical security. This argument runs counter to a common view that the right to physical security is more stringent than the right to the necessities of life. In addition, the common view could be argued to hold that the right to life is a right that is overridden or justly violated only in extreme conditions, while the right to an adequate diet or minimal health care are more easily overridden.

I will also explain why people, in his view, think it is easier to justify rights to security than rights to subsistence and why Shue rejects this reasoning. The actual enjoyment of a substance refers not precisely to enjoyment of the right but rather to enjoyment of what the right provides such as liberty, security, or food. For a right to be socially guaranteed against standard threats arrangements must be made, mostly by a government in the form of laws, for people to enjoy the right.

From this framework, Shue proceeds to define a basic right as right that is essential to the enjoyment of all other rights. As such, non-basic rights such as free speech or assembly may be justifiably sacrificed, if necessary, to protect basic rights.

The question then is what qualifies as a basic right. Shue answers by first arguing that security qualifies as a basic right because no other rights can be enjoyed if a right to physical security is not protected.

The argument is more formally structured as follows: Everyone is entitled to enjoy something as a right. Everyone is entitled to the removal of the most serious and general condition that would prevent or severely interfere with the exercise of whatever rights the person has.

Therefore, anyone who is entitled to anything as a right must be entitled to physical security as a basic right so that threats to his or her physical security cannot be used to thwart the enjoyment of the other right. Shue also claims that the basic right of security is universal because the argument applies to everyone. This is important in his argument for subsistence as a basic right because of the similarity he will draw between security and subsistence. By subsistence or minimal economic security, he means access to unpolluted air, unpolluted water, adequate food, adequate shelter, and minimal preventative health care.

He recognizes that his claim is a form of distributive justice but refrains from treating broader economic rights at this point. In addition, he limits the scope of the basic right of subsistence to at least those who cannot provide for themselves. Both security and subsistence are equally essential to a normal, healthy life and before exercise of other rights are possible. This is not to say that a right to security and subsistence are means to the enjoyment of other rights but are instead inherent necessities.

Shue attempts to show that the common view of accepting security and not subsistence as a basic right lies within the view of negative and positive rights.

A negative right is a right of noninterference or simply leaving people alone while a positive right is giving to others or redistributing wealth.

The prima facie argument against a basic right to subsistence relies on the view that subsistence is a positive right and therefore secondary to the negative right of security. Shue rejects this argument and suggests that both security and subsistence impose positive as well as negative duties. These duties include not depriving the right-holder the object of the right, protection of the right-holder against such deprivation, and aid to those who have already been deprived.

In the case of security, Shue claims that it is impossible to protect a right to physical security without taking or making payment for positive action such as salaries for police officers, judges, and maintenance of correctional facilities.

In the case of subsistence, he shows that fulfillment of the right to subsistence may not involve a redistribution of wealth or grants of commodities but rather protection from individuals or institutions that would otherwise harm them and prevent them from providing for themselves. According to the opposing view, this is a negative right related to security. Shue briefly mentions the cost of security versus the cost of subsistence to further weaken the claim that it subsistence is not a basic right or at least secondary to the right of security.

I will expand upon this concept and show that in many respects, the right to subsistence may actually be cheaper than the right to security. I will also show that the resources of security, like subsistence, favors the rich and therefore also involves a redistribution of wealth to socially guarantee security as a basic right for all. Controversy has surrounded the concept of redistributing wealth for centuries and has been the subject of political philosophers from Immanuel Kant in the 18th century to modern philosophers such as Rawls, Pogge, and Singer.

In regards to the costs associated with the realization of subsistence rights in comparison to actual costs associated with maintaining security rights, the common view is that achieving the right to subsistence would be costly and therefore involve a substantial redistribution of wealth. Based on current spending in the United States alone, I argue that costs necessary to achieve subsistence rights domestically and make a significant increase to achieve international subsistence rights are obtainable without any additional cost to the American taxpayer.

Assuming all U. As Shue has shown, security and subsistence rights both involve positive and negative duties thereby defeating the argument against subsistence rights on the grounds of redistribution of wealth. Further, as the numbers indicate above, a simple shift in expenditures would go far to achieve subsistence as a basic right without any further cost to the American taxpayer.

For example, a 9. One could argue that U. Posted by.

GIUSEPPE TERRAGNI TRANSFORMATIONS DECOMPOSITIONS CRITIQUES PDF

Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy

.

DIGITAL DISRUPTION SHORT FUSE BIG BANG PDF

Basic rights : subsistence, affluence, and U.S. foreign policy

.

GANAPATI ATHARVASHIRSHA IN TELUGU PDF

Basic Rights Subsistence Affluence and U S Foreign Policy

.

Related Articles